Now, I find it very rare to meet anyone, of whatever background, who admits to believing in personal immortality. Still, I think it quite likely that if you asked everyone the question and put pencil and paper in hands, a fairly large number (I am not so free with my percentages as Mr. Dark) would admit the possibility that after death there might be ‘something’. The point Mr. Dark has missed is that the belief, such as it is, hasn't the actuality it had for our forefathers. Never, literally never in recent years, have I met anyone who gave me the impression of believing in the next world as firmly as he believed in the existence of, for instance, Australia. Belief in the next world does not influence conduct as it would if it were genuine. With that endless existence beyond death to look forward to, how trivial our lives here would seem! Most Christians profess to believe in Hell. Yet have you ever met a Christian who seemed as afraid of Hell as he was of cancer? (George Orwell, “As I Please,” Tribune, 14 April 1944)
I was reminded of that comment when reading a book on Ottoman law.1 There were situations in which a defendant could clear himself by swearing an oath. According to the author's account, there were records in the surviving legal documents of capital cases where the defendant refused to swear and was executed as a result, as well as cases where the defendant was convicted of a capital offense on his own voluntary confession. The obvious conclusion is that the defendant must have believed in Heaven and Hell very much as Orwell's contemporaries believed in Australia — and preferred death with a hope of Heaven to a life leading to Hell.
It is the obvious interpretation and the one the author of the book I was reading offered; it may well be correct. But I would want to know more about the situation to be sure.
Imagine someone a few centuries hence looking at records from the American legal system without much knowledge of how it actually worked. Observing that a large majority of felony convictions were by confession, guilty pleas, he might well conclude that 21st century American criminals were so honest, perhaps so afraid of divine punishment for denying their crimes, that they preferred a certainty of prison to a chance of freedom bought at the cost of a lie. What he would be missing would be the institution of plea bargaining, under which a defendant confesses to a lesser charge in exchange for not being tried on a greater, choosing a certainty of (say) one year in prison over a gamble between going free and serving a much longer sentence. The fact that someone pleads guilty not only does not show that he is honest, it does not even show that he is guilty.
We might be missing similar features of the Ottoman case. Islamic religious law, fiqh, does not permit torture. Ottoman law, a fusion of fiqh and Sultanic pronouncements (kanun), did. We do not know, at least I do not know, how voluntary the voluntary confessions were.
For those of us who do not believe in any religion it is tempting to see other people's belief as only semi-real, as more like my belief in the world of The Lord of the Rings (the book, not the movie) than my belief in Australia. It is tempting to interpret our picture of how religious people were in the past as an artifact of filtered data, our sources for the relevant history consisting mostly of accounts written by clerics, a point made by Georges Duby, a prominent medieval historian, in a book that used a rare secular source to provide a balancing picture.2 But it is hard to see how one can give a complete account of either history or the present world without concluding that, for a substantial number of people, Heaven really was, or is, as real as Australia.
How does this apply to contemporary Christian denominations? To what degree do the members believe them, as demonstrated by the degree to which their membership affects their beliefs?
Consider mainline Protestantism. As best I can tell, in the U.S. in my lifetime, mainline Protestants believed the same things those people would have believed if they had not been mainline Protestants, the same things college professors taught and elite media such as the New York Times told them. They were for decolonization, for the War on Poverty, for the Civil Rights movement, against apartheid, ... . Off hand, I cannot think of a single issue on which the dominant position of mainline Protestants was sharply divergent from the position of people of otherwise similar backgrounds who happened to be non-religious Jews, or atheists, or ... .
Contrast to that Catholics. Early in the 20th century, the Catholic church was the one major holdout against the eugenics movement, the project of keeping the unfit from reproducing, a movement whose support ranged from George Bernard Shaw to Winston Churchill. In my lifetime, it has continued to oppose contraception and abortion. It has not yet come to terms with the now widespread acceptance of casual sex.
For a third case, harder to classify, consider Protestant fundamentalists in the U.S.. At first glance they seem to fit the Catholic pattern, rejecting a good deal that the American elite accepts.
But my criterion was not whether people believed what the elite believed but whether they believed what they would have believed absent their religion. For the mainline Protestants, given their cultural and professional backgrounds, those are pretty much the same question. But the base of fundamentalist Protestantism is much more heavily weighted towards small town, rural populations, people that would be skeptical of the beliefs of the New York Times and Harvard professors whatever their religion was. I am not sure to what degree the beliefs of people with that background who happen to be fundamentalists are different from the beliefs of their neighbors who are not.
But Perhaps Not All Catholics
By the time Francis became Pope it was well known in Vatican circles that Cardinal McCarrick had engaged in extensive homosexual activity with young adult seminarians. The previous Pope had, on that account, restricted McCarrick's activities in a variety of ways, details of which are still controversial. When Francis became Pope whatever restrictions had been imposed were lifted and McCarrick became one of the Pope's chief advisers. Then ...
On July 19, 2018, The New York Times published an article based on the story of a man named James, whose last name was withheld. A New Jersey man whose uncle had known McCarrick since high school, James alleged that McCarrick had sexually abused him beginning at age 11. ... On July 27, 2018, Pope Francis ordered McCarrick to observe 'a life of prayer and penance in seclusion' and accepted his resignation from the College of Cardinals.[3] (Wikipedia)
To explain this pattern of events, I offer the following conjectures:
1. Pope Francis, like many moderns, does not regard homosexual activity as morally different from heterosexual activity. His view is in that respect inconsistent with Catholic doctrine and he has prudently concealed it.
2. Pope Francis believes that requiring clerical celibacy is a mistake. This view is inconsistent with current policy but not, as I understand the matter, with theological doctrine.
3. Pope Francis strongly disapproves of adult men having sex with children.
All three of these positions fit modern progressive attitudes, with which Francis seems largely in sympathy. They also explain his behavior. So long as McCarrick's offenses were limited to consensual sex with adults they appeared to Francis insufficiently serious to justify restricting the activities of a talented priest with views on the church close to those of the Pope. Only when evidence of sex with a minor appeared did that change.
So perhaps only some Catholics hold different views than they would hold if they were not Catholics.
Muslims
What about Muslims? Over a period of a century or so the Arabs, who up to then had been bit players in the wars between the Sassinid and Byzantine empires, proceeded to conquer all of the former and more than half of the latter. It was rather as if Poland had set off on a career of conquest in the mid Twentieth Century and ended up ruling all of the USSR and half the U.S.
The obvious explanation is the one offered by Ibn Khaldun in explaining why those events did not fit his historical theories: It was a miracle, due to Allah putting courage into the hearts of the Muslims and fear into their enemies. As Ibn Khaldun pointed out, it is a well established principle that scientific theories do not have to account for miracles, an elegant solution to the problem of explaining away data inconsistent with his theory. Put in a less religious form, if the Arabs were willing to die for their side and the Persians not willing to die for theirs, that could have given the Arabs a considerable military advantage.3
For another approach to the question, one can ask to what degree current Muslims act as if they believe their religion. One of their obligations is a religious tax, zakat, to support the poor, students and six other categories of recipients. As with most tax systems, a clever taxpayer can adjust his behavior to minimize the amount he owes. Someone paying only because the state forces him to, as some Muslim states do, would arrange his affairs to minimize taxes. Someone paying because God will reward or punish on the basis of perfect information about what he does and why or because he believes that he ought to do what God wants should be less willing to game the system.
Zakat consists of two categories. One is a fixed percentage of output for certain agricultural crops — ten percent for crops that are not irrigated, five percent for crops that are. The other is a capital levy of 2.5% on certain forms of wealth: gold, silver, money and a merchant's trade goods.4
Gold and silver are taxable if held as wealth but not, according to three of the four schools of Sunni law, if used as jewelry. Convert your working cash into jewelry, convert it back when needed for your business, and you avoid part of the tax. It would be interesting to see whether Muslim populations in communities that follow the Hanafi school, which holds that gold jewelry is subject to zakat, are less inclined to hold wealth as gold jewelry than populations in other ways similar who follow one of the other three schools.
When I published it in my blog, this was only a research proposal. But one of the commenters provided at least a little relevant information.
I remember reading that in Pakistan, the zakat is enforced by the government on a particular day once a year. In the days leading up to that date, lines at banks are out the door as customers withdraw every penny from their accounts, only to redeposit after the day of reckoning.
Contemporary Muslims who are willing to blow themselves up or fly airplanes into buildings look like evidence in the other direction. But it is hard to be sure to what degree that reflects religious belief, to what degree nationalism. Soldiers in non-religious wars, a kamikaze pilot or a British soldier charging into machine gun fire in a World War One battle, exhibited very similar behavior.
State, Society, and Law in Islam: Ottoman Law in Comparative Perspective by Haim Gerber.
William Marshal: The Flower of Chivalry by Georges Duby.
An alternative explanation of the events I have seen offered is that the two empires had exhausted themselves fighting each other and so were easy prey.
I simplify. Some sources hold that some other forms of wealth also owe zakat. There are other complications, some growing out of the problems of applying seventh century rules to twentieth century societies, which I hope to explore in a later post.
It isn’t the main point of the article but the degree to which plea bargaining is permitted in the US system always disturbs me. Along with the savage sentences for crimes and often useless defence lawyers it seems like an engine for injustice. (It never used to be a thing in the UK but I believe that has changed in recent years).
One thing that's both difficult and interesting to me about this (and that I don't have a good solution for) is the separation of definitions of "christian" in ways that makes sense. On one hand we have what we can call "nominal" christians - people who would at minimum check a box indicating they identify most with christianity out of a list of a bunch of potential religions. On the other hand you have any definition you might want to set that makes any demands greater than that.
The atheist/agnostic thoughtsphere very, very rarely draws any distinction between the former and the latter. Surprisingly often I'll get into an argument where an atheist doesn't like some christien belief or another and relates that he or she has a friend, a very serious Christian, who in fact does not believe in any of the supernatural stuff and thinks that in all cases any rule or guideline of the bible can stand if an only if it doesn't disagree substantially with society. And they are legitimately confused when you point out that there's perhaps a substantial difference between a belief that has any practical implications at all and one that doesn't.
There's a comedian named Pete Holmes who runs a podcast that gets into various religious/spiritual topics a fair bit. He is a fairly apostate Christian - like his backstory is that he got married young, the marriage didn't go well, and in the fallout from that he stopped believing in most of the claims of Christianity. But he at least at some point during the era I listed to his podcast would have still described himself as Christian because he felt like he still sprang from that culture. His phrase for this was that he was "culturally christian", essentially that he still felt some resonance for the trappings of the thing while not substantially believing in it.
I want to have better tools for actually quantifying these differences, but it's harder than it sounds. "Fundamentalist" is mostly read (and broadly used) as a slur - one very common use of the word, despite it's technical definition, is to make Christians who believe any of the bible is binding sound like redneck terrorists. And mainline sounds enough like "mainstream" and is uncommon enough in use in christian/church circles that I'm really unconfident how confounded measurements using that term are.
One sort of imperfect, better-than-nothing solution is to actually deliniate by behavior - i.e. things like looking at church attendence. Famously when you define Christian as "actually shows up to church fairly often", you find Christians suddenly outperform the living hell out of everyone else on metrics like divorce, and stuff like that. I'd be curious to hear takes on other things that work this way - different ways of quantifying "is Christian" that paint different pictures, whether for the better or for the worse.